Thomas
Aquinas, Summa Theologica. Secunda Secundæ Partis: Justice – Q.s 89; 90; 98: On
Oaths; Adjuration and Perjury.
Source: Thomas Aquinas. 1920. The “Summa
Theologica” of St. Thomas Aquinas . Second and Revised Edition. Edited by Roy J Deferrari
and M. Iviolata Barry. Translated by Dominicans. 5 vols. London: Burns, Oates
& Washbourne Ltd. Online Edition 2008 by Kevin Knight, New Advent.
___________________________________________________
Question 89. Oaths
Article 1. Whether to swear is to call God to
witness?
Objection
1. It would
seem that to swear is not to call God to witness. Whoever invokes the authority
of Holy Writ calls God to witness, since it is His word that Holy Writ
contains. Therefore, if to swear is to call God to witness, whoever invoked the
authority of Holy Writ would swear.
But this
is false Therefore the antecedent is false also.
Objection
2. Further,
one does not pay anything to a person by calling him to witness. But he who
swears by God pays something to Him for it is written (Matthew 5:33):
"Thou shall pay [Douay: 'perform'] thy oaths to the Lord"; and Augustine
says [Serm. clxxx] that to swear [jurare] is "to pay the right [jus
reddere] of truth to God." Therefore to swear is not to call God to
witness.
Objection
3. Further,
the duties of a judge differ from the duties of a witness, as shown above
(Q67,70). Now sometimes a man, by swearing, implores the Divine judgment,
according to Psalm 7:5, "If I have rendered to them that repaid me evils,
let me deservedly fall empty before my enemies." Therefore to swear is not
to call God to witness.
On the
contrary, Augustine
says in a sermon on perjury (Serm. clxxx): "When a man says: 'By God,'
what else does he mean but that God is his witness?"
I answer
that, As the Apostle
says (Hebrews 6:16), oaths are taken for the purpose of confirmation. Now
speculative propositions receive confirmation from reason, which proceeds from
principles known naturally and infallibly true. But particular contingent facts
regarding man cannot be confirmed by a necessary reason, wherefore propositions
regarding such things are wont to be confirmed by witnesses. Now a human
witness does not suffice to confirm such matters for two reasons. First, on
account of man's lack of truth, for many give way to lying, according to Psalm
16:10, "Their mouth hath spoken lies [Vulgate: 'proudly']." Secondly,
on account of this lack of knowledge, since he can know neither the future, nor
secret thoughts, nor distant things: and yet men speak about such things, and
our everyday life requires that we should have some certitude about them. Hence
the need to have recourse to a Divine witness, for neither can God lie, nor is
anything hidden from Him. Now to call God to witness is named
"jurare" [to swear] because it is established as though it were a
principle of law [jure] that what a man asserts under the invocation of God as
His witness should be accepted as true. Now sometimes God is called to witness
when we assert present or past events, and this is termed a "declaratory oath";
while sometimes God is called to witness in confirmation of something future,
and this is termed a "promissory oath."
But oaths
are not employed in order to substantiate necessary matters, and such as come
under the investigation of reason; for it would seem absurd in a scientific
discussion to wish to prove one's point by an oath.
Reply to
Objection 1. It is
one thing to employ a Divine witness already given, as when one adduces the
authority of Holy Scripture; and another to implore God to bear witness, as in
an oath.
Reply to
Objection 2. A man is
said to pay his oaths to God because he performs what he swears to do, or
because, from the very fact that he calls upon God to witness, he recognizes
Him as possessing universal knowledge and unerring truth.
Reply to
Objection 3. A person
is called to give witness, in order that he may make known the truth about what
is alleged. Now there are two ways in which God makes known whether the alleged
facts are true or not. On one way He reveals the truth simply, either by inward
inspiration, or by unveiling the facts, namely, by making public what was
hitherto secret: in another way by punishing the lying witness, and then He is
at once judge and witness, since by punishing the liar He makes known his lie.
Hence oaths are of two kinds: one is a simple contestation of God, as when a
man says "God is my witness," or, "I speak before God," or,
"By God," which has the same meaning, as Augustine states [See
argument On the contrary]; the other is by cursing, and consists in a man binding
himself or something of his to punishment if what is alleged be not true.
Article 2. Whether it is lawful to swear?
Objection
1. It would
seem that it is not lawful to swear. Nothing forbidden in the Divine Law is
lawful. Now swearing is forbidden (Matthew 5:34), "But I say to you not to
swear at all"; and (James 5:12), "Above all things, my brethren,
swear not." Therefore swearing is unlawful.
Objection
2. Further,
whatever comes from an evil seems to be unlawful, because according to Matthew
7:18, "neither can an evil tree bring forth good fruit." Now swearing
comes from an evil, for it is written (Matthew 5:37): "But let your speech
be: Yea, yea: No, no. And that which is over and above these is of evil."
Therefore swearing is apparently unlawful.
Objection
3. Further,
to seek a sign of Divine Providence is to tempt God, and this is altogether
unlawful, according to Deuteronomy 6:16, "Thou shalt not tempt the Lord
thy God." Now he that swears seems to seek a sign of Divine Providence,
since he asks God to bear witness, and this must be by some evident effect.
Therefore it seems that swearing is altogether unlawful.
On the
contrary, It is
written (Deuteronomy 6:13): "Thou shalt fear the Lord thy God . . . and
shalt swear by His name."
I answer
that, Nothing
prevents a thing being good in itself, and yet becoming a source of evil to one
who makes use thereof unbecomingly: thus to receive the Eucharist is good, and
yet he that receives it "unworthily, eateth and drinketh judgment to
himself" (1 Corinthians 11:29). Accordingly in answer to the question in
point it must be stated that an oath is in itself lawful and commendable. This
is proved from its origin and from its end. From its origin, because swearing
owes its introduction to the faith whereby man believes that God possesses
unerring truth and universal knowledge and foresight of all things: and from
its end, since oaths are employed in order to justify men, and to put an end to
controversy (Hebrews 6:16).
Yet an oath
becomes a source of evil to him that makes evil use of it, that is who employs
it without necessity and due caution. For if a man calls God as witness, for
some trifling reason, it would seemingly prove him to have but little reverence
for God, since he would not treat even a good man in this manner. Moreover, he
is in danger of committing perjury, because man easily offends in words,
according to James 3:2, "If any man offend not in word, the same is a
perfect man." Wherefore it is written (Sirach 23:9): "Let not thy
mouth be accustomed to swearing, for in it there are many falls."
Reply to
Objection 1. Jerome, commenting
on Matthew 5:34, says: "Observe that our Saviour forbade us to swear, not
by God, but by heaven and earth. For it is known that the Jews have this most evil
custom of swearing by the elements." Yet this answer does not suffice,
because James adds, "nor by any other oath." Wherefore we must reply
that, as Augustine states (De Mendacio xv), "when the Apostle employs an oath
in his epistles, he shows how we are to understand the saying, 'I say to you,
not to swear at all'; lest, to wit, swearing lead us to swear easily and from
swearing easily, we contract the habit, and, from swearing habitually, we fall
into perjury. Hence we find that he swore only when writing, because thought
brings caution and avoids hasty words."
Reply to
Objection 2.
According to Augustine (De Serm. Dom. in Monte i. 17): "If you have to
swear, note that the necessity arises from the infirmity of those whom you
convince, which infirmity is indeed an evil. Accordingly He did not say: 'That
which is over and above is evil,' but 'is of evil.' For you do no evil; since
you make good use of swearing, by persuading another to a useful purpose: yet
it 'comes of the evil' of the person by whose infirmity you are forced to
swear."
Reply to
Objection 3. He who
swears tempts not God, because it is not without usefulness and necessity that
he implores the Divine assistance. Moreover, he does not expose himself to
danger, if God be unwilling to bear witness there and then: for He certainly
will bear witness at some future time, when He "will bring to light the
hidden things of darkness, and will make manifest the counsels of hearts"
(1 Corinthians 4:5). And this witness will be lacking to none who swears,
neither for nor against him.
Article 3. Whether three accompanying conditions of
an oath are suitably assigned, namely, justice, judgment, and truth?
Objection
1. It would
seem that justice, judgment and truth are unsuitably assigned as the conditions
accompanying an oath. Things should not be enumerated as diverse, if one of
them includes the other. Now of these three, one includes another, since truth
is a part of justice, according to Tully (De Invent. Rhet. ii, 53): and
judgment is an act of justice, as stated above (Question 60, Article 1).
Therefore the three accompanying conditions of an oath are unsuitably assigned.
Objection
2. Further,
many other things are required for an oath, namely, devotion, and faith whereby
we believe that God knows all things and cannot lie. Therefore the accompanying
conditions of an oath are insufficiently enumerated.
Objection
3. Further,
these three are requisite in man's every deed: since he ought to do nothing
contrary to justice and truth, or without judgment, according to 1 Timothy 5:21,
"Do nothing without prejudice," i.e. without previous judgment [Vulgate:
'Observe these things without prejudice, doing nothing by declining to either
side.']. Therefore these three should not be associated with an oath any more
than with other human actions.
On the
contrary, It is
written (Jeremiah 4:2): "Thou shalt swear: As the Lord liveth, in truth,
and in judgment, and in justice": which words Jerome expounds, saying:
"Observe that an oath must be accompanied by these conditions, truth,
judgment and justice."
I answer
that, As
stated above (Article 2), an oath is not good except for one who makes good use
of it. Now two conditions are required for the good use of an oath. First, that
one swear, not for frivolous, but for urgent reasons, and with discretion; and
this requires judgment or discretion on the part of the person who swears.
Secondly, as regards the point to be confirmed by oath, that it be neither false,
nor unlawful, and this requires both truth, so that one employ an oath in order
to confirm what is true, and justice, so that one confirm what is lawful. A
rash oath lacks judgment, a false oath lacks truth, and a wicked or unlawful oath
lacks justice.
Reply to
Objection 1. Judgment
does not signify here the execution of justice, but the judgment of discretion,
as stated above. Nor is truth here to be taken for the part of justice, but for
a condition of speech.
Reply to
Objection 2.
Devotion, faith and like conditions requisite for the right manner of swearing
are implied by judgment: for the other two regard the things sworn to as stated
above. We might also reply that justice regards the reason for swearing.
Reply to
Objection 3. There is
great danger in swearing, both on account of the greatness of God Who is called
upon to bear witness, and on account of the frailty of the human tongue, the
words of which are confirmed by oath. Hence these conditions are more requisite
for an oath than for other human actions.
Article 4. Whether an oath is an act of religion or
latria?
Objection
1. It would
seem that an oath is not an act of religion, or latria. Acts of religion are
about holy and divine things. But oaths are employed in connection with human
disputes, as the Apostle declares (Hebrews 6:16). Therefore swearing is not an
act of religion or latria.
Objection
2. Further,
it belongs to religion to give worship to God, as Tully says (De Invent. Rhet.
ii, 53). But he who swears offers nothing to God, but calls God to be his
witness. Therefore swearing is not an act of religion or latria.
Objection
3. Further,
the end of religion or latria is to show reverence to God. But the end of an oath
is not this, but rather the confirmation of some assertion. Therefore swearing
is not an act of religion.
On the
contrary, It is
written (Deuteronomy 6:13): "Thou shalt fear the Lord thy God, and shalt
serve Him only, and thou shalt swear by His name." Now he speaks there of
the servitude of religion. Therefore swearing is an act of religion.
I answer
that, As
appears from what has been said above (Article 1), he that swears calls God to
witness in confirmation of what he says. Now nothing is confirmed save by what
is more certain and more powerful. Therefore in the very fact that a man swears
by God, he acknowledges God to be more powerful, by reason of His unfailing truth
and His universal knowledge; and thus in a way he shows reverence to God. For
this reason the Apostle says (Hebrews 6:16) that "men swear by one greater
than themselves," and Jerome commenting on Matthew 5:34, says that
"he who swears either reveres or loves the person by whom he swears."
The Philosopher, too, states (Metaph. i, 3) that "to swear is to give very
great honor." Now to show reverence to God belongs to religion or latria.
wherefore it is evident that an oath is an act of religion or latria.
Reply to
Objection 1. Two
things may be observed in an oath. The witness adduced, and this is Divine: and
the thing witnessed to, or that which makes it necessary to call the witness,
and this is human. Accordingly an oath belongs to religion by reason of the
former, and not of the latter.
Reply to
Objection 2. In the
very fact that a man takes God as witness by way of an oath, he acknowledges
Him to be greater: and this pertains to the reverence and honor of God, so that
he offers something to God, namely, reverence and honor.
Reply to
Objection 3. Whatsoever
we do, we should do it in honor of God: wherefore there is no hindrance, if by
intending to assure a man, we show reverence to God. For we ought so to perform
our actions in God's honor that they may conduce to our neighbor's good, since God
also works for His own glory and for our good.
Article 5. Whether oaths are desirable and to be
used frequently as something useful and good?
Objection
1. It would
seem that oaths are desirable and to be used frequently as something useful and
good. Just as a vow is an act of religion, so is an oath. Now it is commendable
and more meritorious to do a thing by vow, because a vow is an act of religion,
as stated above (Question 88, Article 5). Therefore for the same reason, to do
or say a thing with an oath is more commendable, and consequently oaths are
desirable as being good essentially.
Objection
2. Further,
Jerome, commenting on Matthew 5:34, says that "he who swears either
reveres or loves the person by whom he swears." Now reverence and love of God
are desirable as something good essentially. Therefore swearing is also.
Objection
3. Further,
swearing is directed to the purpose of confirming or assuring. But it is a good
thing for a man to confirm his assertion. Therefore an oath is desirable as a good
thing.
On the
contrary, It is
written (Sirach 23:12): "A man that sweareth much shall be filled with iniquity":
and Augustine says (De Mendacio xv) that "the Lord forbade swearing, in
order that for your own part you might not be fond of it, and take pleasure in
seeking occasions of swearing, as though it were a good thing."
I answer
that, Whatever
is required merely as a remedy for an infirmity or a defect, is not reckoned
among those things that are desirable for their own sake, but among those that
are necessary: this is clear in the case of medicine which is required as a
remedy for sickness. Now an oath is required as a remedy to a defect, namely,
some man's lack of belief in another man. Wherefore an oath is not to be reckoned
among those things that are desirable for their own sake, but among those that
are necessary for this life; and such things are used unduly whenever they are
used outside the bounds of necessity. For this reason Augustine says (De Serm.
Dom. in Monte i, 17): "He who understands that swearing is not to be held
as a good thing," i.e. desirable for its own sake, "restrains himself
as far as he can from uttering oaths, unless there be urgent need."
Reply to
Objection 1. There is
no parity between a vow and an oath: because by a vow we direct something to
the honor of God, so that for this very reason a vow is an act of religion. On
the other hand, in an oath reverence for the name of God is taken in
confirmation of a promise. Hence what is confirmed by oath does not, for this
reason, become an act of religion, since moral acts take their species from the
end.
Reply to
Objection 2. He who
swears does indeed make use of his reverence or love for the person by whom he
swears: he does not, however, direct his oath to the reverence or love of that person,
but to something else that is necessary for the present life.
Reply to
Objection 3. Even as
a medicine is useful for healing, and yet, the stronger it is, the greater harm
it does if it be taken unduly, so too an oath is useful indeed as a means of
confirmation, yet the greater the reverence it demands the more dangerous it
is, unless it be employed aright; for, as it is written (Sirach 23:13),
"if he make it void," i.e. if he deceive his brother, "his sin
shall be upon him: and if he dissemble it," by swearing falsely, and with
dissimulation, "he offendeth double," [because, to wit,
"pretended equity is a twofold iniquity," as Augustine [Enarr. in
Psalm 63:7] declares: "and if he swear in vain," i.e. without due cause
and necessity, "he shall not be justified."
Article 6. Whether it is lawful to swear by
creatures?
Objection
1. It would
seem that it is not lawful to swear by creatures. It is written (Matthew
5:34-36): "I say to you not to swear at all, neither by heaven . . . nor
by the earth . . . nor by Jerusalem . . . nor by thy head": and Jerome,
expounding these words, says: "Observe that the Saviour does not forbid
swearing by God, but by heaven and earth," etc.
Objection
2. Further,
punishment is not due save for a fault. Now a punishment is appointed for one
who swears by creatures: for it is written (22, qu. i, can. Clericum): "If
a cleric swears by creatures he must be very severely rebuked: and if he shall
persist in this vicious habit we wish that he be excommunicated."
Therefore it is unlawful to swear by creatures.
Objection
3. Further,
an oath is an act of religion, as stated above (Article 4).
But
religious worship is not due to any creature, according to Romans 1:23-25.
Therefore it is not lawful to swear by a creature.
On the
contrary, Joseph
swore "by the health of Pharaoh" (Genesis 42:16). Moreover it is
customary to swear by the Gospel, by relics, and by the saints.
I answer
that, As
stated above (1, ad 3), there are two kinds of oath. One is uttered a simple
contestation or calling God as witness: and this kind of oath, like faith, is
based on God's truth. Now faith is essentially and chiefly about God Who is the
very truth, and secondarily about creatures in which God's truth is reflected,
as stated above (Question 1, Article 1). On like manner an oath is chiefly
referred to God Whose testimony is invoked; and secondarily an appeal by oath
is made to certain creatures considered, not in themselves, but as reflecting
the Divine truth. Thus we swear by the Gospel, i.e. by God Whose truth is made known
in the Gospel; and by the saints who believed this truth and kept it.
The other
way of swearing is by cursing and in this kind of oath a creature is adduced
that the judgment of God may be wrought therein. Thus a man is wont to swear by
his head, or by his son, or by some other thing that he loves, even as the Apostle
swore (2 Corinthians 1:23), saying: "I call God to witness upon my soul."
As to Joseph's
oath by the health of Pharaoh this may be understood in both ways: either by
way of a curse, as though he pledged Pharao's health to God; or by way of
contestation, as though he appealed to the truth of God's justice which the
princes of the earth are appointed to execute.
Reply to
Objection 1. Our Lord
forbade us to swear by creatures so as to give them the reverence due to God.
Hence Jerome adds that "the Jews, through swearing by the angels and the
like, worshipped creatures with a Divine honor."
In the
same sense a cleric is punished, according to the canons (22, qu. i, can.
Clericum, Objection 2), for swearing by a creature, for this savors of the blasphemy
of unbelief. Hence in the next chapter, it is said: "If any one swears by God's
hair or head, or otherwise utter blasphemy against God, and he be in
ecclesiastical orders, let him be degraded."
This
suffices for the Reply to the Second Objection.
Reply to
Objection 3.
Religious worship is shown to one whose testimony is invoked by oath: hence the
prohibition (Exodus 23:13): "By the name of strange gods you shall not
swear." But religious worship is not given to creatures employed in an oath
in the ways mentioned above.
Article 7. Whether an oath has a binding force?
Objection
1. It would
seem that an oath has no binding force. An oath is employed in order to confirm
the truth of an assertion. But when a person makes an assertion about the
future his assertion is true, though it may not be verified. Thus Paul lied not
(2 Corinthians 1:15, seqq.) though he went not to Corinth, as he had said he
would (1 Corinthians 16:5). Therefore it seems that an oath is not binding.
Objection
2. Further,
virtue is not contrary to virtue (Categ. viii, 22). Now an oath is an act of virtue,
as stated above (Article 4). But it would sometimes be contrary to virtue, or
an obstacle thereto, if one were to fulfil what one has sworn to do: for
instance, if one were to swear to commit a sin, or to desist from some virtuous
action. Therefore an oath is not always binding.
Objection
3. Further,
sometimes a man is compelled against his will to promise something under oath.
Now, "such a person is loosed by the Roman Pontiffs from the bond of his oath"
(Extra, De Jurejur., cap. Verum in ea quaest., etc.). Therefore an oath is not
always binding.
Objection
4. Further,
no person can be under two opposite obligations. Yet sometimes the person who swears
and the person to whom he swears have opposite intentions. Therefore an oath
cannot always be binding.
On the
contrary, It is
written (Matthew 5:33): "Thou shalt perform thy oaths to the Lord."
I answer
that, An obligation
implies something to be done or omitted; so that apparently it regards neither
the declaratory oath (which is about something present or past), nor such oaths
as are about something to be effected by some other cause (as, for example, if
one were to swear that it would rain tomorrow), but only such as are about
things to be done by the person who swears.
Now just
as a declaratory oath, which is about the future or the present, should contain
the truth, so too ought the oath which is about something to be done by us in
the future. Yet there is a difference: since, in the oath that is about the
past or present, this obligation affects, not the thing that already has been
or is, but the action of the swearer, in the point of his swearing to what is
or was already true; whereas, on the contrary, in the oath that is made about
something to be done by us, the obligation falls on the thing guaranteed by oath.
For a man is bound to make true what he has sworn, else his oath lacks truth.
Now if
this thing be such as not to be in his power, his oath is lacking in judgment
of discretion: unless perchance what was possible when he swore become
impossible to him through some mishap. as when a man swore to pay a sum of
money, which is subsequently taken from him by force or theft. For then he
would seem to be excused from fulfilling his oath, although he is bound to do
what he can, as, in fact, we have already stated with regard to the obligation
of a vow (88, 3, ad 2). If, on the other hand, it be something that he can do,
but ought not to, either because it is essentially evil, or because it is a
hindrance to a good, then his oath is lacking in justice: wherefore an oath
must not be kept when it involves a sin or a hindrance to good. For in either
case "its result is evil" [Cf. Bede, Homil. xix, in Decoll. S. Joan.
Bapt.]
Accordingly
we must conclude that whoever swears to do something is bound to do what he can
for the fulfilment of truth; provided always that the other two accompanying conditions
be present, namely, judgment and justice.
Reply to
Objection 1. It is
not the same with a simple assertion, and with an oath wherein God is called to
witness: because it suffices for the truth of an assertion, that a person say
what he proposes to do, since it is already true in its cause, namely, the
purpose of the doer. But an oath should not be employed, save in a matter about
which one is firmly certain: and, consequently, if a man employ an oath, he is
bound, as far as he can, to make true what he has sworn, through reverence of
the Divine witness invoked, unless it leads to an evil result, as stated.
Reply to
Objection 2. An oath
may lead to an evil result in two ways. First, because from the very outset it
has an evil result, either through being evil of its very nature (as, if a man
were to swear to commit adultery), or through being a hindrance to a greater good,
as if a man were to swear not to enter religion, or not to become a cleric, or
that he would not accept a prelacy, supposing it would be expedient for him to
accept, or in similar cases. For oaths of this kind are unlawful from the
outset: yet with a difference: because if a man swear to commit a sin, he sinned
in swearing, and sins in keeping his oath: whereas if a man swear not to
perform a greater good, which he is not bound to do withal, he sins indeed in
swearing (through placing an obstacle to the Holy Ghost, Who is the inspirer of
good purposes), yet he does not sin in keeping his oath, though he does much
better if he does not keep it.
Secondly,
an oath leads to an evil result through some new and unforeseen emergency. An
instance is the oath of Herod, who swore to the damsel, who danced before him,
that he would give her what she would ask of him. For this oath could be lawful
from the outset, supposing it to have the requisite conditions, namely, that
the damsel asked what it was right to grant. but the fulfilment of the oath was
unlawful. Hence Ambrose says (De Officiis i, 50): "Sometimes it is wrong
to fulfil a promise, and to keep an oath; as Herod, who granted the slaying of
John, rather than refuse what he had promised."
Reply to
Objection 3. There is
a twofold obligation in the oath which a man takes under compulsion: one,
whereby he is beholden to the person to whom he promises something; and this obligation
is cancelled by the compulsion, because he that used force deserves that the
promise made to him should not be kept. The other is an obligation whereby a
man is beholden to God, in virtue of which he is bound to fulfil what he has
promised in His name. This obligation is not removed in the tribunal of conscience,
because that man ought rather to suffer temporal loss, than violate his oath.
He can, however, seek in a court of justice to recover what he has paid, or
denounce the matter to his superior even if he has sworn to the contrary,
because such an oath would lead to evil results since it would be contrary to
public justice. The Roman Pontiffs, in absolving men from oaths of this kind,
did not pronounce such oaths to be unbinding, but relaxed the obligation for
some just cause.
Reply to
Objection 4. When the
intention of the swearer is not the same as the intention of the person to whom
he swears, if this be due to the swearer's guile, he must keep his oath in
accordance with the sound understanding of the person to whom the oath is made.
Hence Isidore says (De Summo Bono ii, 31): "However artful a man may be in
wording his oath, God Who witnesses his conscience accepts his oath as
understood by the person to whom it is made." And that this refers to the
deceitful oath is clear from what follows: "He is doubly guilty who both
takes God's name in vain, and tricks his neighbor by guile." If, however,
the swearer uses no guile, he is bound in accordance with his own intention.
Wherefore Gregory says (Moral. xxvi, 7): "The human ear takes such like
words in their natural outward sense, but the Divine judgment interprets them
according to our inward intention."
Article 8. Whether an oath is more binding than a
vow?
Objection
1. It would
seem that an oath is more binding than a vow. A vow is a simple promise:
whereas an oath includes, besides a promise, an appeal to God as witness.
Therefore an oath is more binding than a vow.
Objection
2. Further,
the weaker is wont to be confirmed by the stronger. Now a vow is sometimes
confirmed by an oath. Therefore an oath is stronger than a vow.
Objection
3. Further,
the obligation of a vow arises from the deliberation of the mind, a stated
above (Question 88, Article 1); while the obligation of an oath results from
the truth of God Whose testimony is invoked. Since therefore God's truth is
something greater than human deliberation, it seems that the obligation of an oath
is greater than that of a vow.
On the
contrary, A vow
binds one to God while an oath sometimes binds one to man. Now one is more
bound to God than to man. Therefore a vow is more binding than an oath.
I answer
that, The obligation
both of vow and of an oath arises from something Divine; but in different ways.
For the obligation of a vow arises from the fidelity we owe God, which binds us
to fulfil our promises to Him. On the other hand, the obligation of an oath
arises from the reverence we owe Him which binds us to make true what we
promise in His name. Now every act of infidelity includes an irreverence, but
not conversely, because the infidelity of a subject to his lord would seem to
be the greatest irreverence. Hence a vow by its very nature is more binding
than an oath.
Reply to
Objection 1. A vow is
not any kind of promise, but a promise made to God; and to be unfaithful to God
is most grievous.
Reply to
Objection 2. An oath
is added to a vow not because it is more stable, but because greater stability
results from "two immutable things" [Hebrews 6:18.
Reply to
Objection 3.
Deliberation of the mind gives a vow its stability, on the part of the person
who takes the vow: but it has a greater cause of stability on the part of God,
to Whom the vow is offered.
Article 9. Whether anyone can dispense from an
oath?
Objection
1. It would
seem that no one can dispense from an oath. Just as truth is required for a
declaratory oath, which is about the past or the present, so too is it required
for a promissory oath, which is about the future. Now no one can dispense a man
from swearing to the truth about present or past things. Therefore neither can
anyone dispense a man from making truth that which he has promised by oath to
do in the future.
Objection
2. Further,
a promissory oath is used for the benefit of the person to whom the promise is
made. But, apparently, he cannot release the other from his oath, since it
would be contrary to the reverence of God. Much less therefore can a dispensation
from this oath be granted by anyone.
Objection
3. Further,
any bishop can grant a dispensation from a vow, except certain vows reserved to
the Pope alone, as stated above (88, 12, ad 3). Therefore in like manner, if an
oath admits of dispensation, any bishop can dispense from an oath. And yet
seemingly this is to be against the law [Caus. XV, qu. 6, can. Auctoritatem,
seqq.: Cap. Si vero, de Jurejurando]. Therefore it would seem that an oath does
not admit of dispensation.
On the
contrary, A vow is
more binding than an oath, as stated above (Article 8). But a vow admits of
dispensation and therefore an oath does also.
I answer
that, As
stated above (Question 88, Article 10), the necessity of a dispensation both
from the law and from a vow arises from the fact that something which is useful
and morally good in itself and considered in general, may be morally evil and
hurtful in respect of some particular emergency: and such a case comes under
neither law nor vow. Now anything morally evil or hurtful is incompatible with
the matter of an oath: for if it be morally evil it is opposed to justice, and
if it be hurtful it is contrary to judgment. Therefore an oath likewise admits
of dispensation.
Reply to
Objection 1. A
dispensation from an oath does not imply a permission to do anything against
the oath: for this is impossible, since the keeping of an oath comes under a
Divine precept, which does not admit of dispensation: but it implies that what
hitherto came under an oath no longer comes under it, as not being due matter
for an oath, just as we have said with regard to vows (88, 10, ad 2). Now the matter
of a declaratory oath, which is about something past or present, has already
acquired a certain necessity, and has become unchangeable, wherefore the
dispensation will regard not the matter but the act itself of the oath: so that
such a dispensation would be directly contrary to the Divine precept. On the
other hand, the matter of a promissory oath is something future, which admits
of change, so that, to wit, in certain emergencies, it may be unlawful or
hurtful, and consequently undue matter for an oath. Therefore a promissory oath
admits of dispensation, since such dispensation regards the matter of an oath,
and is not contrary to the Divine precept about the keeping of oaths.
Reply to
Objection 2. One man
may promise something under oath to another in two ways. First, when he promises
something for his benefit: for instance, if he promise to serve him, or to give
him money: and from such a promise he can be released by the person to whom he
made it: for he is understood to have already kept his promise to him when he
acts towards him according to his will. Secondly, one man promises another
something pertaining to God's honor or to the benefit of others: for instance,
if a man promise another under oath that he will enter religion, or perform
some act of kindness. On this case the person to whom the promise is made
cannot release him that made the promise, because it was made principally not
to him but to God: unless perchance it included some condition, for instance,
"provided he give his consent" or some such like condition.
Reply to
Objection 3.
Sometimes that which is made the matter of a promissory oath is manifestly
opposed to justice, either because it is a sin, as when a man swears to commit
a murder, or because it is an obstacle to a greater good, as when a man swears
not to enter a religion: and such an oath requires no dispensation. But in the
former case a man is bound not to keep such an oath, while in the latter it is
lawful for him to keep or not to keep the oath, as stated above (07, ad 2).
Sometimes what is promised on oath is doubtfully right or wrong, useful or
harmful, either in itself or under the circumstance. On this case any bishop
can dispense. Sometimes, however, that which is promised under oath is
manifestly lawful and beneficial. An oath of this kind seemingly admits not of
dispensation but of commutation, when there occurs something better to be done
for the common good, in which case the matter would seem to belong chiefly to
the power of the Pope, who has charge over the whole Church; and even of
absolute relaxation, for this too belongs in general to the Pope in all matters
regarding the administration of things ecclesiastical. Thus it is competent to
any man to cancel an oath made by one of his subjects in matters that come
under his authority: for instance, a father may annul his daughter's oath, and
a husband his wife's (Numbers 30:6, seqq.), as stated above with regard to vows
(88, A8,9).
Article 10. Whether an oath is voided by a
condition of person or time?
Objection
1. It would
seem that an oath is not voided by a condition of person or time. An oath,
according to the Apostle (Hebrews 6:16), is employed for the purpose of
confirmation. Now it is competent to anyone to confirm his assertion, and at
any time. Therefore it would seem that an oath is not voided by a condition of person
or time.
Objection
2. Further,
to swear by God is more than to swear by the Gospels: wherefore Chrysostom
[Hom. xliv in the Opus Imperfectum falsely ascribed to St. John Chrysostom]
says: "If there is a reason for swearing, it seems a small thing to swear
by God, but a great thing to swear by the Gospels. To those who think thus, it
must be said: Nonsense! the Scriptures were made for God's sake, not God for
the sake of the Scriptures." Now men of all conditions and at all times
are wont to swear by God. Much more, therefore, is it lawful to swear by the Gospels.
Objection
3. Further,
the same effect does not proceed from contrary causes, since contrary causes
produce contrary effects. Now some are debarred from swearing on account of
some personal defect; children, for instance, before the age of fourteen, and persons
who have already committed perjury. Therefore it would seem that a person ought
not to be debarred from swearing either on account of his dignity, as clerics,
or on account of the solemnity of the time.
Objection
4. Further,
in this world no living man is equal in dignity to an angel: for it is written
(Matthew 11:11) that "he that is the lesser in the kingdom of heaven is
greater than he," namely than John the Baptist, while yet living. Now an angel
is competent to swear, for it is written (Apocalypse 10:6) that the angel
"swore by Him that liveth for ever and ever." Therefore no man ought
to be excused from swearing, on account of his dignity.
On the
contrary, It is
stated (II, qu. v, can. Si quis presbyter): "Let a priest be examined 'by
his sacred consecration,' instead of being put on his oath": and (22, qu.
v, can. Nullus): "Let no one in ecclesiastical orders dare to swear on the
Holy Gospels to a layman."
I answer
that, Two
things are to be considered in an oath. One is on the part of God, whose
testimony is invoked, and in this respect we should hold an oath in the
greatest reverence. For this reason children before the age of puberty are
debarred from taking oaths [Caus. XXII, qu. 5, can. Parvuli], and are not
called upon to swear, because they have not yet attained the perfect use of reason,
so as to be able to take a oath with due reverence. Perjurers also are debarred
from taking an oath, because it is presumed from their antecedents that they will
not treat an oath with the reverence due to it. For this same reason, in order
that oaths might be treated with due reverence the law says (22, qu. v, can.
Honestum): "It is becoming that he who ventures to swear on holy things
should do so fasting, with all propriety and fear of God."
The other
thing to be considered is on the part of the man, whose assertion is confirmed
by oath. For a man's assertion needs no confirmation save because there is a doubt
about it. Now it derogates from a person's dignity that one should doubt about
the truth of what he says, wherefore "it becomes not persons of great
dignity to swear." For this reason the law says (II, qu. v, can. Si quis
presbyter) that "priests should not swear for trifling reasons."
Nevertheless it is lawful for them to swear if there be need for it, or if
great good may result therefrom. Especially is this the case in spiritual
affairs, when moreover it is becoming that they should take oath on days of solemnity,
since they ought then to devote themselves to spiritual matters. Nor should
they on such occasions take oaths temporal matters, except perhaps in cases
grave necessity.
Reply to
Objection 1. Some are
unable to confirm their own assertions on account of their own defect: and some
there are whose words should be so certain that they need no confirmation.
Reply to
Objection 2. The
greater the thing sworn by, the holier and the more binding is the oath,
considered in itself, as Augustine states (Ad Public., Ep. xlvii): and
accordingly is a graver matter to swear by God than the Gospels. Yet the
contrary may be the case on account of the manner of swearing for instance, an oath
by the Gospels might be taken with deliberation and solemnity, and an oath by God
frivolously and without deliberation.
Reply to
Objection 3. Nothing
prevents the same thing from arising out of contrary causes, by way of
superabundance and defect. It is in this way that some are debarred from
swearing, through being of so great authority that it is unbecoming for them to
swear; while others are of such little authority that their oaths have no
standing.
Reply to
Objection 4. The angel's
oath is adduced not on account of any defect in the angel, as though one ought
not to credit his mere word, but in order to show that the statement made
issues from God's infallible disposition. Thus too God is sometimes spoken of
by Scripture as swearing, in order to express the immutability of His word, as
the Apostle declares (Hebrews 6:17).
Question 90. The
taking of God's name by way of adjuration
Article 1. Whether it is lawful to adjure a man?
Objection 1. It would seem that it is not lawful to adjure
a man. Origen says (Tract. xxxv super Matth.): "I deem that a man who
wishes to live according to the Gospel should
not adjure another man. For if, according to the
Gospel mandate of Christ, it be unlawful to swear,
it is evident that neither is it lawful to adjure:
and consequently it is manifest that the high-priest unlawfully adjured
Jesus by the living God."
Objection 2. Further, whoever adjures
a man, compels him after a fashion. But it is unlawful to compel a man against
his will. Therefore seemingly it is also
unlawful to adjure a man.
Objection 3. Further, to adjure
is to induce a person to swear. Now it belongs
to man's superior to induce him to swear, for
the superior imposes an oath on his subject. Therefore subjects cannot adjure
their superiors.
On the contrary, Even when we pray God we implore Him by certain
holy things: and the Apostle too besought the faithful
"by the mercy of God" (Romans 12:1): and this seems to be a kind of adjuration.
Therefore it is lawful to adjure.
I answer that, A man who utters a promissory oath, swearing
by his reverence for the Divine name, which he
invokes in confirmation of his promise,
binds himself to do what he has undertaken, and so orders
himself unchangeably to do a certain thing. Now
just as a man can order himself to do a certain
thing, so too can he order others, by beseeching
his superiors, or by commanding his inferiors, as stated above (Question
83, Article 1). Accordingly when either of these orderings is
confirmed by something Divine it is an adjuration.
Yet there is this difference between them, that man is master of his own actions
but not of those of others; wherefore he can put himself under an obligation by
invoking the Divine name, whereas he cannot put
others under such an obligation unless they be his subjects, whom he can compel
on the strength of the oath they have taken.
Therefore, if a man by invoking the name of God, or any holy thing, intends
by this adjuration to put one who is not his
subject under an obligation to do a certain thing, in the same way as he would
bind himself by oath, such an adjuration is
unlawful, because he usurps over another a power which he has not. But
superiors may bind their inferiors by this kind of adjuration,
if there be need for it.
If, however, he merely intend, through
reverence of the Divine name or of some holy thing, to obtain something from
the other man without putting him under any obligation, such an adjuration
may be lawfully employed in respect of anyone.
Reply to Objection 1. Origen is speaking of an adjuration
whereby a man intends to put another under an obligation,
in the same way as he would bind himself by oath: for thus did the high-priest presume
to adjure our Lord Jesus Christ [Matthew 26:63].
Reply to Objection 2. This argument considers the adjuration
which imposes an obligation.
Reply to Objection 3. To adjure
is not to induce a man to swear, but to employ
terms resembling an oath in order to provoke another to do a certain
thing.
Moreover, we adjure God in one way and man in
another; because when we adjure a man we intend
to alter his will by appealing to his reverence
for a holy thing: and we cannot have such an intention in respect of God Whose will
is immutable. If we obtain something from God through His eternal will,
it is due, not to our merits, but to His goodness.
Article 2. Whether it is lawful to adjure the demons?
Objection 1. It would seem unlawful to adjure
the demons. Origen says (Tract. xxxv, super Matth.): "To adjure
the demons is not accordance with the power given by our Saviour:
for this is a Jewish practice." Now rather
than imitate the rites of the Jews, we should
use the power given by Christ. Therefore it is not lawful to adjure
the demons.
Objection 2. Further, many make use of necromantic
incantations when invoking the demons by something Divine: and this is an adjuration.
Therefore, if it be lawful to adjure the demons,
it is lawful to make use of necromantic incantations, which is evidently false.
Therefore the antecedent is false also.
Objection 3. Further, whoever adjures
a person, by that very fact associates himself with him. Now it is not lawful
to have fellowship with the demons, according to 1 Corinthians 10:20, "I
would not that you should be made partakers with devils." Therefore it is
not lawful to adjure the demons.
On the contrary, It is written (Mark 16:17): "In My
name they shall cast out devils." Now to induce anyone to do a certain
thing for the sake of God's name is to adjure.
Therefore it is lawful to adjure the demons.
I answer that, As stated in the preceding article,
there are two ways of adjuring: one by way of prayer
or inducement through reverence of some holy thing: the other by way of
compulsion. On the first way it is not lawful to adjure
the demons because such a way seems to savor of benevolence or friendship,
which it is unlawful to bear towards the demons. As to the second kind of adjuration,
which is by compulsion, we may lawfully use it for some purposes, and not for
others. For during the course of this life the demons are our adversaries: and
their actions are not subject to our disposal
but to that of God and the holy angels, because, as Augustine says (De Trin.
iii, 4), "the rebel spirit is ruled by the
just spirit." Accordingly we may repulse
the demons, as being our enemies, by adjuring
them through the power of God's name, lest they
do us harm of soul or body, in accord with the Divine power given by Christ, as
recorded by Luke 10:19: "Behold, I have given you power to tread upon
serpents and scorpions, and upon all the power of the enemy: and nothing shall
hurt you."
It is not, however, lawful to adjure them for
the purpose of learning something from them, or of obtaining something through
them, for this would amount to holding fellowship with them: except perhaps
when certain holy men,
by special instinct or Divine revelation, make use of the demons' actions
in order to obtain certain results: thus we read
of the Blessed James
[the Greater; cf. Apocrypha,
N.T., Hist. Certam. Apost. vi, 19 that he caused Hermogenes to be brought to
him, by the instrumentality of the demons.
Reply to Objection 1. Origen is speaking of adjuration
made, not authoritatively by way of compulsion, but rather by way of a friendly
appeal.
Reply to Objection 2. Necromancers
adjure and invoke the demons in order to obtain
or learn something from them: and this is unlawful, as stated above. Wherefore Chrysostom,
commenting on our Lord's words to the unclean spirit
(Mark 1:25), "Speak no more, and go out of the man," says: "A salutary
teaching is given us here, lest we believe the demons, however much they speak
the truth."
Reply to Objection 3. This argument considers the adjuration
whereby the demon's help is besought in doing or learning something: for this
savors of fellowship with them. On the other hand, to repulse the demons by adjuring
them, is to sever oneself from their fellowship.
Article 3. Whether it is lawful to adjure an irrational
creature?
Objection 1. It would seem unlawful to adjure
an irrational creature. An adjuration consists
of spoken words. But it is useless to speak to one that understands not, such
as an irrational creature. Therefore it is vain and unlawful to adjure
an irrational creature.
Objection 2. Further, seemingly wherever adjuration
is admissible, swearing is also admissible. But swearing
is not consistent with an irrational creature. Therefore it would seem unlawful
to employ adjuration towards one.
Objection 3. Further, there are two ways of adjuring,
as explained above (1 and 2).
One is by way of appeal; and this cannot be
employed towards irrational creatures, since they are not masters of their own actions.
The other kind of adjuration is by way of
compulsion: and, seemingly, neither is it lawful to use this towards them,
because we have not the power to command irrational creatures, but only He of
Whom it was said (Matthew 8:27): "For the winds and the sea obey
Him." Therefore in no way, apparently, is it lawful to adjure
irrational creatures.
On the contrary, Simon and Jude
are related to have adjured dragons and to have
commanded them to withdraw into the desert.
[From the apocryphal Historiae Certam. Apost. vi. 19.]
I answer that, Irrational creatures are directed to their
own actions by some other agent. Now the action
of what is directed and moved is also the action
of the director and mover: thus the movement of the arrow is an operation of
the archer. Wherefore the operation of the irrational creature is ascribed not
only to it, but also and chiefly to God, Who disposes the movements of all
things. It is also ascribed to the devil, who, by God's permission, makes use
of irrational creatures in order to inflict harm on man.
Accordingly the adjuration of an irrational
creature may be of two kinds. First, so that the adjuration
is referred to the irrational creature in itself: and in this way it would be
vain to adjure an irrational creature. Secondly,
so that it be referred to the director and mover of the irrational creature,
and in this sense a creature of this kind may be adjured
in two ways. First, by way of appeal made to God,
and this relates to those who work miracles by calling on God: secondly, by way
of compulsion, which relates to the devil, who uses the irrational creature for
our harm. This is the kind of adjuration used in
the exorcisms of the Church, whereby the power
of the demons is expelled from an irrational creature. But it is not lawful to adjure
the demons by beseeching them to help us.
This suffices for the Replies to the Objections.
Question 98.
Perjury
Article 1. Whether it is necessary for perjury that
the statement confirmed on oath be false?
Objection
1. It would
seem that it is not necessary for perjury that the statement confirmed on oath
be false. As stated above (Question 89, Article 3), an oath should be
accompanied by judgment and justice no less than by truth. Since therefore
perjury is incurred through lack of truth, it is incurred likewise through lack
of judgment, as when one swears indiscreetly, and through lack of justice, as
when one swears to something unjust.
Objection
2. Further,
that which confirms is more weighty than the thing confirmed thereby: thus in a
syllogism the premises are more weighty than the conclusion. Now in an oath a
man's statement is confirmed by calling on the name of God. Therefore perjury
seems to consist in swearing by false gods rather than in a lack of truth in
the human statement which is confirmed on oath.
Objection
3. Further,
Augustine says (De Verb. Apost. Jacobi; Serm. clxxx): "Men swear falsely
both in deceiving others and when they are deceived themselves"; and he
gives three examples. The first is: "Supposing a man to swear, thinking
that what he swears to is true, whereas it is false"; the second is:
"Take the instance of another who knows the statement to be false, and
swears to it as though it were true"; and the third is: "Take
another, who thinks his statement false, and swears to its being true, while
perhaps it is true," of whom he says afterwards that he is a perjurer.
Therefore one may be a perjurer while swearing to the truth. Therefore
falsehood is not necessary for perjury.
On the
contrary, Perjury
is defined "a falsehood confirmed by oath" [Hugh of St. Victor, Sum.
Sent. iv, 5.
I answer
that, As
stated above (Question 92, Article 2), moral acts take their species from their
end. Now the end of an oath is the confirmation of a human assertion. To this
confirmation falsehood is opposed: since an assertion is confirmed by being
firmly shown to be true; and this cannot happen to that which is false. Hence
falsehood directly annuls the end of an oath: and for this reason, that
perversity in swearing, which is called perjury, takes its species chiefly from
falsehood. Consequently falsehood is essential to perjury.
Reply to
Objection 1. As Jerome
says on Jeremiah 4:2, "whichever of these three be lacking, there is
perjury," but in different order. For first and chiefly perjury consists
in a lack of truth, for the reason stated in the Article. Secondly, there is
perjury when justice is lacking, for in whatever way a man swears to that which
is unlawful, for this very reason he is guilty of falsehood, since he is under
an obligation to do the contrary. Thirdly, there is perjury when judgment is
lacking, since by the very fact that a man swears indiscreetly, he incurs the
danger of lapsing into falsehood.
Reply to
Objection 2. In
syllogisms the premises are of greater weight, since they are in the position
of active principle, as stated in Phys. ii, 3: whereas in moral matters the end
is of greater importance than the active principle. Hence though it is a
perverse oath when a man swears to the truth by false gods, yet perjury takes
its name from that kind of perversity in an oath, that deprives the oath of its
end, by swearing what is false.
Reply to
Objection 3. Moral
acts proceed from the will, whose object is the apprehended good. Wherefore if
the false be apprehended as true, it will be materially false, but formally true,
as related to the will. If something false be apprehended as false, it will be false
both materially and formally. If that which is true be apprehended as false, it
will be materially true, and formally false. Hence in each of these cases the conditions
required for perjury are to be found in some way, on account of some measure of
falsehood. Since, however, that which is formal in anything is of greater
importance than that which is material, he that swears to a falsehood thinking
it true is not so much of a perjurer as he that swears to the truth thinking it
false. For Augustine says (De Verb. Apost. Jacobi; Serm. clxxx): "It
depends how the assertion proceeds from the mind, for the tongue is not guilty
except the mind be guilty."
Article 2. Whether all perjury is sinful?
Objection
1. It would
seem that not all perjury is sinful. Whoever does not fulfil what he has
confirmed on oath is seemingly a perjurer. Yet sometimes a man swears he will
do something unlawful (adultery, for instance, or murder): and if he does it,
he commits a sin. If therefore he would commit a sin even if he did it not, it
would follow that he is perplexed.
Objection
2. Further,
no man sins by doing what is best. Yet sometimes by committing a perjury one
does what is best: as when a man swears not to enter religion, or not to do
some kind of virtuous deed. Therefore not all perjury is sinful.
Objection
3. Further,
he that swears to do another's will would seem to be guilty of perjury unless
he do it. Yet it may happen sometimes that he sins not, if he do not the man's
will: for instance, if the latter order him to do something too hard and
unbearable. Therefore seemingly not all perjury is sinful.
Objection
4. Further,
a promissory oath extends to future, just as a declaratory oath extends to past
and present things. Now the obligation of an oath may be removed by some future
occurrence: thus a state may swear to fulfil some obligation, and afterwards
other citizens come on the scene who did not take the oath; or a canon may
swear to keep the statutes of a certain church, and afterwards new statutes are
made. Therefore seemingly he that breaks an oath does not sin.
On the
contrary, Augustine
says (De Verb. Apost. Jacobi; Serm. cxxx), in speaking of perjury: "See
how you should detest this horrible beast and exterminate it from all human
business."
I answer
that, As
stated above (Question 89, Article 1), to swear is to call God as witness. Now
it is an irreverence to God to call Him to witness to a falsehood, because by
so doing one implies either that God ignores the truth or that He is willing to
bear witness to a falsehood. Therefore perjury is manifestly a sin opposed to
religion, to which it belongs to show reverence to God.
Reply to
Objection 1. He that
swears to do what is unlawful is thereby guilty of perjury through lack of justice:
though, if he fails to keep his oath, he is not guilty of perjury in this
respect, since that which he swore to do was not a fit matter of an oath.
Reply to
Objection 2. A person
who swears not to enter religion, or not to give an alms, or the like, is
guilty of perjury through lack of judgment. Hence when he does that which is
best it is not an act of perjury, but contrary thereto: for the contrary of
that which he is doing could not be a matter of an oath.
Reply to
Objection 3. When one
man swears or promises to do another's will, there is to be understood this
requisite condition--that the thing commanded be lawful and virtuous, and not
unbearable or immoderate.
Reply to
Objection 4. An oath
is a personal act, and so when a man becomes a citizen of a state, he is not
bound, as by oath, to fulfil whatever the state has sworn to do. Yet he is
bound by a kind of fidelity, the nature of which obligation is that he should
take his share of the state's burdens if he takes a share of its goods.
The canon
who swears to keep the statutes that have force in some particular
"college" is not bound by his oath to keep any that may be made in
the future, unless he intends to bind himself to keep all, past and future.
Nevertheless he is bound to keep them by virtue of the statutes themselves,
since they are possessed of coercive force, as stated above (I-II, 96, 4).
Article 3. Whether all perjury is a mortal sin?
Objection
1. It would
seem that not all perjury is a mortal sin. It is laid down (Extra, De Jurejur,
cap. Verum): "Referring to the question whether an oath is binding on
those who have taken one in order to safeguard their life and possessions, we
have no other mind than that which our predecessors the Roman Pontiffs are known
to have had, and who absolved such persons from the obligations of their oath.
Henceforth, that discretion may be observed, and in order to avoid occasions of
perjury, let them not be told expressly not to keep their oath: but if they
should not keep it, they are not for this reason to be punished as for a mortal
sin." Therefore not all perjury is a mortal sin.
Objection
2. Further,
as Chrysostom [Hom. xliv in the Opus Imperfectum on St. Matthew, falsely
ascribed to St. John Chrysostom] says, "it is a greater thing to swear by God
than by the Gospels." Now it is not always a mortal sin to swear by God to
something false; for instance, if we were to employ such an oath in fun or by a
slip of the tongue in the course of an ordinary conversation. Therefore neither
is it always a mortal sin to break an oath that has been taken solemnly on the Gospels.
Objection
3. Further,
according to the Law a man incurs infamy through committing perjury (VI, qu. i,
cap. Onfames). Now it would seem that infamy is not incurred through any kind
of perjury, as it is prescribed in the case of a declaratory oath violated by perjury
[Cap. Cum dilectus, de Ord. Cognit.]. Therefore, seemingly, not all perjury is
a mortal sin.
On the
contrary, Every sin
that is contrary to a divine precept is a mortal sin. Now perjury is contrary
to a divine precept, for it is written (Leviticus 19:12): "Thou shalt not
swear falsely by My name." Therefore it is a mortal sin.
I answer
that,
According to the teaching of the Philosopher (Poster. i, 2), "that which causes
a thing to be such is yet more so." Now we know that an action which is,
by reason of its very nature, a venial sin, or even a good action, is a mortal sin
if it be done out of contempt of God. Wherefore any action that of its nature,
implies contempt of God is a mortal sin. Now perjury, of its very nature
implies contempt of God, since, as stated above (Article 2), the reason why it
is sinful is because it is an act of irreverence towards God. Therefore it is
manifest that perjury, of its very nature, is a mortal sin.
Reply to
Objection 1. As
stated above (89, 07, ad 3), coercion does not deprive a promissory oath of its
binding force, as regards that which can be done lawfully. Wherefore he who
fails to fulfil an oath which he took under coercion is guilty of perjury and sins
mortally. Nevertheless the Sovereign Pontiff can, by his authority, absolve a
man from an obligation even of an oath, especially if the latter should have
been coerced into taking the oath through such fear as may overcome a
high-principled man.
When,
however, it is said that these persons are not to be punished as for a mortal sin,
this does not mean that they are not guilty of mortal sin, but that a lesser
punishment is to be inflicted on them.
Reply to
Objection 2. He that
swears falsely in fun is nonetheless irreverent to God, indeed, in a way, he is
more so, and consequently is not excused from mortal sin. He that swears falsely
by a slip of tongue, if he adverts to the fact that he is swearing, and that he
is swearing to something false, is not excused from mortal sin, as neither is
he excused from contempt of God. If, however, he does not advert to this, he
would seem to have no intention of swearing, and consequently is excused from
the sin of perjury.
It is,
however, a more grievous sin to swear solemnly by the Gospels, than to swear by
God in ordinary conversation, both on account of scandal and on account of the
greater deliberation. But if we consider them equally in comparison with one
another, it is more grievous to commit perjury in swearing by God than in
swearing by the Gospels.
Reply to
Objection 3. Not
every sin makes a man infamous in the eye of the law. Wherefore, if a man who
has sworn falsely in a declaratory oath be not infamous in the eye of the law,
but only when he has been so declared by sentence in a court of law, it does
not follow that he has not sinned mortally. The reason why the law attaches
infamy rather to one who breaks a promissory oath taken solemnly is that he
still has it in his power after he has sworn to substantiate his oath, which is
not the case in a declaratory oath.
Article 4. Whether he sins who demands an oath of a
perjurer?
Objection
1. It would
seem that he who demands an oath of a perjurer commits a sin. Either he knows
that he swears truly, or he knows that he swears falsely. If he knows him to
swear truly, it is useless for him to demand an oath: and if he believes him to
swear falsely, for his own part he leads him into sin. Therefore nowise
seemingly should one enjoin an oath on another person.
Objection
2. Further,
to receive an oath from a person is less than to impose an oath on him. Now it
would seem unlawful to receive an oath from a person, especially if he swear falsely,
because he would then seem to consent in his sin. Much less therefore would it
seem lawful to impose an oath on one who swears falsely.
Objection
3. Further,
it is written (Leviticus 5:1): "If anyone sin, and hear the voice of one
swearing falsely ['Falsely' is not in the Vulgate'], and is a witness either
because he himself hath seen, or is privy to it: if he do not utter it, he
shall bear his iniquity." Hence it would seem that when a man knows
another to be swearing falsely, he is bound to denounce him. Therefore it is
not lawful to demand an oath of such a man.
Objection
4. On the
other hand, Just as it is a sin to swear falsely so is it to swear by false
gods. Yet it is lawful to take advantage of an oath of one who has sworn by false
gods, as Augustine says (ad Public. Ep. xlvii). Therefore it is lawful to
demand an oath from one who swears falsely.
I answer
that, As
regards a person who demands an oath from another, a distinction would seem to
be necessary. For either he demands the oath on his own account and of his own
accord, or he demands it on account of the exigencies of a duty imposed on him.
If a man demands an oath on his own account as a private individual, we must
make a distinction, as does Augustine (de Perjuriis. serm. clxxx): "For if
he knows not that the man will swear falsely, and says to him accordingly: 'Swear
to me' in order that he may be credited, there is no sin: yet it is a human temptation"
(because, to wit, it proceeds from his weakness in doubting whether the man
will speak the truth). "This is the evil whereof Our Lord says (Matthew
5:37): That which is over and above these, is of evil. But if he knows the man
to have done so," i.e. the contrary of what he swears to, "and yet
forces him to swear, he is a murderer: for the other destroys himself by his
perjury, but it is he who urged the hand of the slayer."
If, on
the other hand, a man demands an oath as a public person, in accordance with
the requirements of the law, on the requisition of a third person: he does not
seem to be at fault, if he demands an oath of a person, whether he knows that
he will swear falsely or truly, because seemingly it is not he that exacts the oath
but the person at whose instance he demands it.
Reply to
Objection 1. This
argument avails in the case of one who demands an oath on his own account. Yet
he does not always know that the other will swear truly or falsely, for at
times he has doubts about the fact, and believes he will swear truly. On such a
case he exacts an oath in order that he may be more certain.
Reply to
Objection 2. As Augustine
says (ad Public. serm. xlvii), "though we are forbidden to swear, I do not
remember ever to have read in the Holy Scriptures that we must not accept oaths
from others." Hence he that accepts an oath does not sin, except perchance
when of his own accord he forces another to swear, knowing that he will swear falsely.
Reply to
Objection 3. As Augustine
says (QQ. Super Lev, qu. i), Moses in the passage quoted did not state to whom
one man had to denounce another's perjury: wherefore it must be understood that
the matter had to be denounced "to those who would do the perjurer good
rather than harm." Again, neither did he state in what order the
denunciation was to be made: wherefore seemingly the Gospel order should be
followed, if the sin of perjury should be hidden, especially when it does not
tend to another person's injury: because if it did, the Gospel order would not
apply to the case, as stated above (33, 07; 68, 1).
Reply to
Objection 4. It is
lawful to make use of an evil for the sake of good, as God does, but it is not
lawful to lead anyone to do evil. Consequently it is lawful to accept the oath
of one who is ready to swear by false gods, but it is not lawful to induce him
to swear by false gods. Yet it seems to be different in the case of one who
swears falsely by the true God, because an oath of this kind lacks the good of faith,
which a man makes use of in the oath of one who swears truly by false gods, as Augustine
says (ad Public. Ep. xlvii). Hence when a man swears falsely by the true God
his oath seems to lack any good that one may use lawfully.
No comments:
Post a Comment